Note: For any geometry problem whose statement begins with an asterisk , the first page of the solution must be a large, in-scale, clearly labeled diagram. Failure to meet this requirement will result in an automatic 1-point deduction.
There are bowls arranged in a row, numbered
through
, where
and
are given positive integers. Initially, each of the first
bowls contains an apple, and each of the last
bowls contains a pear.
A legal move consists of moving an apple from bowl to bowl
and a pear from bowl
to bowl
, provided that the difference
is even. We permit multiple fruits in the same bowl at the same time. The goal is to end up with the first
bowls each containing a pear and the last
bowls each containing an apple. Show that this is possible if and only if the product
is even.
Let be the set of all integers. Find all pairs of integers
for which there exist functions
and
satisfying
for all integers
.
Let
be a cyclic quadrilateral satisfying
. The diagonals of
intersect at
. Let
be a point on side
satisfying
. Show that line
bisects
.
Let
be a triangle with
obtuse. The
-excircle is a circle in the exterior of
that is tangent to side
of the triangle and tangent to the extensions of the other two sides. Let
be the feet of the altitudes from
and
to lines
and
, respectively. Can line
be tangent to the
-excircle?
Let be a nonnegative integer. Determine the number of ways that one can choose
sets
, for integers
with
such that:
for all
, the set
has
elements; and
whenever
and
Two rational numbers and
are written on a blackboard, where
and
are relatively prime positive integers. At any point, Evan may pick two of the numbers
and
written on the board and write either their arithmetic mean
or their harmonic mean
on the board as well. Find all pairs
such that Evan can write
on the board in finitely many steps.
Claim: If and
are both odd, then the end goal of achieving
pears followed by
apples is impossible.
Proof: Let and
denote the number of apples and the number of pears in odd-numbered positions, respectively. We show that
is invariant. Notice that if
and
are odd, then
and
both decrease by 1, as one apple and one pear are both moved from odd-numbered positions to even-numbered positions. If
and
are even, then
and
both increase by 1.
Because the starting configuration has
odd-numbered apples and
odd-numbered pears, the initial value of
is
. But the desired ending configuration has
odd-numbered pears and
odd-numbered apples, so
. As
is invariant, it is impossible to attain the desired ending configuration.
Claim: If at least one of and
is even, then the end goal of achieving
pears followed by
apples is possible.
Proof: Without loss of generality, assume is even. If only
is even, then we can number the bowls in reverse, and swap apples with pears. We use two inductive arguments to show that
is achievable for all
, then to show that
is achievable for all even
and all
.
Base case: . Then we can easily achieve the ending configuration in two moves, by moving the apple in bowl #1 and the pear in bowl #3 so that everything is in bowl #2, then finishing the next move.
Inductive step: suppose that for (even) apples and
pears, that with
apples and
pears, the ending configuration is achievable. We will show two things: i) achievable with
apples and
pears, and ii) achievable with
apples and
pears.
i) Apply the process on the apples and first
pairs to get a configuration
. Now we will "swap" the leftmost apple with the last pear by repeatedly applying the move on just these two fruits (as
is even, the difference
is even). This gives a solution for
apples and
pears. In particular, this shows that
for all
is achievable.
ii) To show is achievable, given that
is achievable, apply the process on the last
apples and
pears to get the configuration
. Then, because we have shown that 2 apples and
pears is achievable in i), we can now reverse the first two apples and
pears.
Thus for even, the desired ending configuration is achievable.
Combining the above two claims, we see that this is possible if and only if is even.
"If" part: Note that two opposite fruits can be switched if they have even distance. If one of ,
is odd and the other is even, then switch
with
,
with
,
with
... until all of one fruit is switched. If both are even, then if
, then switch
with
,
with
,
with
... until all of one fruit is switched; if
then switch
with
,
with
,
with
... until all of one fruit is switched. Each of these processes achieve the end goal.
"Only if" part: Assign each apple a value of and each pear a value of
. At any given point in time, let
be the sum of the values of the fruit in even-numbered bowls. Because
and
both are odd, at the beginning there are
apples in even bowls and
pears in even bowls, so at the beginning
. After the end goal is achieved, there are
apples in even bowls and
pears in even bowls, so after the end goal is achieved
. However, because two opposite fruits must have the same parity to move and will be the same parity after they move, we see that
is invariant, which is a contradiction; hence, it is impossible for the end goal to be reached if
is odd.
We claim that the answer is .
Proof: and
are surjective because
and
can take on any integral value, and by evaluating the parentheses in different order, we find
and
. We see that if
then
to
as well, so similarly if
then
, so now assume
.
We see that if then
, if
then
, if
then
... if
then
. This means that the
-element collection
contains all
residues mod
since
is surjective, so
. Doing the same to
yields that
, so this means that only
can work.
For let
and
, and for
let
and
, so
does work and are the only solutions, as desired.
Let . Also, let
be the midpoint of
.
Note that only one point satisfies the given angle condition. With this in mind, construct
with the following properties:
Claim:
Proof:
The conditions imply the similarities and
whence
as desired.
Claim: is a symmedian in
Proof:
We have
as desired.
Since is the isogonal conjugate of
,
. However
implies that
is the midpoint of
from similar triangles, so we are done.
~sriraamster
By monoticity, we can see that the point is unique. Therefore, if we find another point
with all the same properties as
, then
Part 1) Let be a point on
such that
, and
. Obviously
exists because adding the two equations gives
, which is the problem statement. Notice that converse PoP gives
Therefore,
, so
does indeed satisfy all the conditions
does, so
. Hence,
and
.
Part 2) Define as the midpoint of
. Furthermore, create a point
such that
and
. Obviously
must be a parallelogram. Now we set up for Jacobi's. The problem already gives us that
, which is good for starters. Furthermore,
tells us that
This gives us our second needed angle equivalence. Lastly,
will give
which is our last necessary angle equivalence to apply Jacobi's. Finally, applying Jacobi's tells us that
,
, and
are concurrent
,
,
collinear. Additionally, since parallelogram diagonals bisect each other,
,
, and
are collinear, so finally we obtain that
,
, and
are collinear, as desired.
Instead of trying to find a synthetic way to describe being tangent to the
-excircle (very hard), we instead consider the foot of the perpendicular from the
-excircle to
, hoping to force something via the length of the perpendicular. It would be nice if there were an easier way to describe
, something more closely related to the
-excircle; as we are considering perpendicularity, if we could generate a line parallel to
, that would be good.
So we recall that it is well known that triangle is similar to
. This motivates reflecting
over the angle bisector at
to obtain
, which is parallel to
for obvious reasons.
Furthermore, as reflection preserves intersection, is tangent to the reflection of the
-excircle over the
-angle bisector. But it is well-known that the
-excenter lies on the
-angle bisector, so the
-excircle must be preserved under reflection over the
-excircle. Thus
is tangent to the
-excircle.Yet for all lines parallel to
, there are only two lines tangent to the
-excircle, and only one possibility for
, so
.
Thus as is isoceles,
contradiction. -alifenix-
The answer is no.
Suppose otherwise. Consider the reflection over the bisector of . This swaps rays
and
; suppose
and
are sent to
and
. Note that the
-excircle is fixed, so line
must also be tangent to the
-excircle.
Since is cyclic, we obtain
, so
. However, as
is a chord in the circle with diameter
,
.
If then
too, so then
lies inside
and cannot be tangent to the excircle.
The remaining case is when . In this case,
is also a diameter, so
is a rectangle. In particular
. However, by the existence of the orthocenter, the lines
and
must intersect, contradiction.
Note that there are ways to choose
, because there are
ways to choose which number
is,
ways to choose which number to append to make
,
ways to choose which number to append to make
... After that, note that
contains the
in
and 1 other element chosen from the 2 elements in
not in
so there are 2 ways for
. By the same logic there are 2 ways for
as well so
total ways for all
, so doing the same thing
more times yields a final answer of
.
There are ways to choose
. Since, there are
ways to choose
, and after that, to generate
, you take
and add 2 new elements, getting you
ways to generate
. And you can keep going down the line, and you get that there are
ways to pick
Then we can fill out the rest of the gird. First, let’s prove a lemma.
Claim: If we know what is and what
is, then there are 2 choices for both
and
.
Proof: Note and
, so
. Let
be a set that contains all the elements in
that are not in
.
. We know
contains total
elements. And
contains total
elements. That means
contains only 2 elements since
. Let’s call these 2 elements
.
.
contains 1 elements more than
and 1 elements less than
. That 1 elements has to select from
. It’s easy to see
or
, so there are 2 choice for
. Same thing applies to
.
We used our proved lemma, and we can fill in then we can fill in the next diagonal, until all
are filled, where
. But, we haven’t finished everything! Fortunately, filling out the rest of the diagonals in a similar fashion is pretty simple. And, it’s easy to see that we have made
decisions, each with 2 choices, when filling out the rest of the grid, so there are
ways to finish off.
To finish off, we have ways to fill in the gird, which gets us
We claim that all odd work if
is a positive power of 2.
Proof: We first prove that works. By weighted averages we have that
can be written, so the solution set does indeed work. We will now prove these are the only solutions.
Assume that , so then
for some odd prime
. Then
, so
. We see that the arithmetic mean is
and the harmonic mean is
, so if 1 can be written then
and
which is obviously impossible, and we are done.
完整版真题资料可以底部二维码免费领取↓↓↓
翰林课程体验,退费流程快速投诉邮箱: yuxi@linstitute.net 沪ICP备2023009024号-1